Informacja

Drogi użytkowniku, aplikacja do prawidłowego działania wymaga obsługi JavaScript. Proszę włącz obsługę JavaScript w Twojej przeglądarce.

Wyszukujesz frazę "Pawlikowski, Tomasz" wg kryterium: Autor


Wyświetlanie 1-14 z 14
Tytuł:
Problem prawdy u Wilhelma z Owernii
The problem of truth according to William of Auvergne
Autorzy:
Pawlikowski, Tomasz
Powiązania:
https://bibliotekanauki.pl/articles/496287.pdf
Data publikacji:
2012
Wydawca:
Towarzystwo Naukowe Franciszka Salezego
Tematy:
Medieval Philosophy
Truth
Future Contingents
Metaphysics
Logic
Opis:
William of Auvergne (1180–1249) was one of the first wave professors of University in Paris to engage with Greek, Islamic and Jewish philosophical writings that had become available in Latin translation. He was the author of a vast work that he calls the Magisterium divinale (Teaching on God). De universo (On the Universe), written in the 1230s, is the most philosophical treatise of the Magisterium. One short part (I, 3, 25-26) of this treatise includes a very important philosophical topic – the problem of truth. Based on a doctrine of Avicenna, William formulated one of the forms of truth's classical definition. In his view, this definition express the essence of logical truth, which is constituted in any relation between human intellect and things, if intellect is adequate to his object. So the logical truth is a basis and property of true judgments and statements about all real things, and even about what really does not exist (things in the future, in the past, non-beings, negations), and – generally – about all the man can think or about everything possible to thinking. William rejects the doctrine of St. Augustine, who taught that every truth has its source in the First Truth identified with God the Creator of all things and intellects contingent. William argues that only actually existing things are real existing as caused by God. So only actually existing things can be substrates of truth and so subjects of true judgments and statements. The Creator doesn't cause things as existing in the past, in the future, but as existing in the present. What is more, He doesn't cause non-beings and negations. In consequence, William recognizes logical truth as the only justification for true adjudication of all what exists and doesn't exist. In Steven P. Marrone's opinion William's theory of truth is a new idea in the early thirteenth century. He believes that William's theory, however incomplete, explains how much the problem of truth is depended on logic rather than metaphysics, so that it could be separated radically from questions of being and viewed independently of the issue concerning the relation of the mind and creatures to God. In fact, although William continued to speak in traditional terms, he divorced with the point of view of ontology and natural theology, finding solutions in theories of logic and language. However, taken in this article studies seem to show that William's theory of truth is embedded in a metaphysical context. Furthermore, medieval logic is the science of the action of the intellect, which is a faculty of human being. This is not logic in twentieth-century's sense. Thus, it does not seem to William resigned from metaphysics to logic. His theory of logical truth is imperfect because of metaphysical errors. The main error is that the logical truth, which realizes in the relation of intellect to things and so is one of truths that exist in contingent beings, William considered as final and the sole basis of every true judgments and statements, without regard to its dependence on the First Truth. Indeed, logical truth is not able to truly independent existence.
Źródło:
Seminare. Poszukiwania naukowe; 2012, 31; 87-102
1232-8766
Pojawia się w:
Seminare. Poszukiwania naukowe
Dostawca treści:
Biblioteka Nauki
Artykuł
Tytuł:
Spójność teorii partycypacji zawartej w tekstach świętego Tomasza z Akwinu
Consistency of the theory of participation contained in the texts of Saint Thomas Aquinas
Autorzy:
Pawlikowski, Tomasz
Powiązania:
https://bibliotekanauki.pl/articles/2016246.pdf
Data publikacji:
2000
Wydawca:
Katolicki Uniwersytet Lubelski Jana Pawła II. Towarzystwo Naukowe KUL
Opis:
W swoim artykule stawiam pytanie, czy teoria partycypacji, którą można znaleźć w pismach św. Tomasza z Akwinu, w swoich podstawowych punktach zgadza się z jego metafizyką. Aby odpowiedzieć na to pytanie, analizuję kilka tekstów doktora Anielskiego, poświęconych problematyce partycypacji.Po przeprowadzeniu badań mogę stwierdzić, że u św. Tomasza teoria partycypacji opiera się na koncepcji aktu i władzy, i obejmuje wszystkie stopnie bytu, jak w dwóch innych jego wielkich teoriach, to znaczy w teorii przyczynowości i teorii analogii, które są fundamentalnymi punktami całej jego nauki.Widzimy więc, że teoria partycypacji jest integralną i naprawdę ważną częścią doktryny metafizycznej doktora Anielskiego, chociaż wiemy, że jest to kwestia, która zrodziła się w szkole platonistów i neoplatonistów. La cohérence de la théorie de la participation présentée dans des écrits de Saint Thomas d’Aquin Dans mon article, je pose la question si la théorie de la participation, qui se trouve dans des écrits de Saint Thomas d’Aquin, s’accorde à sa métaphysique en ses lignes fondamentales. Pour répondre à cette question, j’analyse plusieurs textes de Docteur Angélique consacres à la problématique de la participation.Après mes recherches, je peux dire que chez Saint Thomas la théorie de la participation est fondée sur la conception de l’acte et de la puissance, et qu’elle comprend tous les degrés de l’être, comme dans deux ses autres grandes théories, c'est-à-dire, la théorie de la causalité et la théorie de l’analogie, qui sont des points fondamentaux de tout son enseignement.On voit donc que la théorie de la participation est un élément intégral et vraiment important de la doctrine métaphysique de Docteur Angélique, bien que l’on sache que c ’est une question qui est issue de l’école des Platoniciens et Neo-Platoniciens.
In my article, I ask the question whether the theory of participation found in the writings of Saint Thomas Aquinas, complies with his metaphysics in its fundamental lines. To answer this question, I analyze several texts by Doctor Angelic devoted to the issue of participation. After my research, I conclude that Aquinas' theory of participation is founded on the concepts of the act and power, and that it includes all the degrees of being, as in two of his other great theories: the theory of causation and the theory of analogy, which are fundamental points of all his teaching. We see then, that the theory of participation is an integral and really important part of the metaphysical doctrine of Doctor Angelic, although we know that this is a question which came from the Platonists and Neo-Platonists.
Źródło:
Roczniki Filozoficzne; 2000, 48, 1; 103-126
0035-7685
Pojawia się w:
Roczniki Filozoficzne
Dostawca treści:
Biblioteka Nauki
Artykuł
Tytuł:
Klasyczne ujęcia problemu prawdy w „post-świecie”
The Classic Approaches to the Problem of Truth in the “Post-World”
Autorzy:
Pawlikowski, Tomasz
Powiązania:
https://bibliotekanauki.pl/articles/2075958.pdf
Data publikacji:
2018-12-30
Wydawca:
Naukowe Towarzystwo Tomistyczne
Tematy:
prawda
filozofia współczesna
tomizm
arystotelizm
platonizm
Truth
Contemporary Philosophy
Thomism
Aristotelianism
Platonism
Opis:
1. For many people, the contemporary culture seems to be something different from modernity, it is something resembling a special period of “post-”. At the same time, different trends are present in current culture. Some reach the genesis of nearly two and a half thousand years back, others have about half a century. Perhaps also breaks some modern belief that in every culture, “newer” means “better”. 2. Representatives of the philosophical and theological trend of “Radical Orthodoxy” noticed in this the approach of postmodernism to the pre-modern tradition. Therefore, we can say that we live and operate in a “post-world”, without leading currents of thought. On the other hand, is the current culture very different from the others when you look at it from the perspective of centuries? 3. For many philosophers, it is still important to reach to the great traditional approaches to the problem of truth. These are above all three concepts related to three great philosophical syntheses created by Plato, Aristotle and Saint Thomas Aquinas. This is also evident among the basic contemporary trends critical of the classics and philosophical tradition. 4. M. Heidegger created a certain idea of being reduced to the time determinant. For the supporters of his views, it became the overcoming of Aquinas’s theory. The German thinker also formulated a specific interpretation of Plato's views on truth. He contrasted it with Thomas's concept, especially with the definition of truth as the adequacy of thing to intellect. 5. T. Bartoś – Polish author of the new attempt to read the essence of the concept – believes, in turn, that the statements of the Angelic Doctor can be found close to the characteristics of post-modernity. He points to a certain incoherence and fragmentary nature of the problem, anthropocentrism and pragmatism of the approach, and a rejection of the unity of truth. It seems, however, that there is a lot of exaggeration in this interpretation. De facto, we are dealing here with radical criticism of Thomism as a trend that develops the views of Saint Thomas Aquinas, because none of the known Thomists do not even come close in their deliberations to the view that T. Bartoś formulated. 6. Finally, a group of philosophers using in the method of reflection the achievements of contemporary logic, representatives of analytic philosophy, generally seems to be aimed at getting rid of the term “truth” from his vocabulary. The idea of reaching their assumptions of logical positivism is difficult to discuss with his followers because of the difference in approach to the practice of philosophy itself between the “analysts” and “non-analysts”. The classic concept of philosophy, under which situates itself Platonism, Aristotelianism and Thomism, is different from the concept of linguistic or neo-positivist, which locates to analytic philosophy. 7. The classical approach to truth, especially the definition developed in the final shape in the Middle Ages, indicating the adequacy of things and the intellect as the essence of truth, therefore meets with criticism from various directions. This does not mean that they should go into oblivion, that they have been replaced by newer and better concepts, or simply refuted. The proclamation of the slogans such as “The End of the Era ...”, “The End of Truth ...” sounds propaganda. 8. The classical approach to the problem of truth has lost nothing in its argumentation. In fact, the current forms of criticism do not rely on any discussion, but on the rejection of the principles on which it is based. Heidegger proclaimed his vision of being and truth, supporting it with a hermeneutic analysis of ancient works. He claimed that this vision is contained in the properly read outlooks of ancient Greek thinkers. The current of philosophy practiced with the use of modern logic tools considers reality only in so far as it can be translated into a “language fact”. This is the analysis of language and not reality. The proposal to read the theory of truth contained in the works of Aquinas, submitted by T. Bartoś to be a projection of some interpretative grid on the expression Thomas's interpretation, wherein the radically differs from the recognized positions. 9. It seems that in the whirlwind of ideologies present in philosophy, science and culture in general, it remains to preserve the classical approach to the problem of truth and develop them according to their essential elements. Compilation with principles that are not appropriate to them will not result in the presentation of their authentic content. They are permanent achievements of culture, philosophically justified. Recourse to reality, confrontation with it, makes the classic approaches open in terms of development. None of them provides a closed system also adopted a priori or received by the conversion performed according to a specified number of regulations. The development of the classical approaches to the problem of truth is theoretically interesting for the whole field of philosophy and as such should be supported.
Źródło:
Rocznik Tomistyczny; 2018, 7; 313-344
2300-1976
Pojawia się w:
Rocznik Tomistyczny
Dostawca treści:
Biblioteka Nauki
Artykuł
Tytuł:
Poznawalność bytu. Parmenides i św. Tomasz z Akwinu
Cognoscibility of Being. Case of Parmenides and St. Thomas Aquinas
Autorzy:
Pawlikowski, Tomasz
Powiązania:
https://bibliotekanauki.pl/articles/452395.pdf
Data publikacji:
2013
Wydawca:
Naukowe Towarzystwo Tomistyczne
Tematy:
byt
poznawalność bytu
metafizyka
św. Tomasz z Akwinu
Parmenides
being
cognoscibility of being
metaphysics
St. Thomas Aquinas
Opis:
According to Parmenides, the only acceptable way of philosophy as true cognition is research of being. The philosophical tradition had taken this track. St. Thomas Aquinas had very little information about Parmenidean ontology, but shared his focus on being as the object of knowledge. However, they had a different understanding of being. Philosopher of Elea claimed that everything is one monistic being. Therefore, every act of cognition has the same object – being. There is only being. Non-being is nothing. It doesn’t exist, so it isn’t cognizable. Moreover, the knowledge of being and being itself are the same. As a consequence, Parmenides described entity in identification to the mind and recognized the essence of being as truth. Therefore, his ontology is called “a veridical conception of being”. According to Aquinas, being is pluralistic. There are many types of entities, minds and truths. The core of every being is act of existence. The truth is property of singular beings or judgements. Thomas metaphysics is existential. The truth, that is here identified with adequation of thing and intellect, and cognoscibility of beings, is interpreted as the consequence of existence. Being, truth and cognoscibility are different things. In comparison with Parmenides, Thomas seems to be more faithful to the “way of being”. He characterizes being as existing and avoids a specific paradox that is inability to define the truth in a classical way, assuming her identity with the entity.
Źródło:
Rocznik Tomistyczny; 2013, 2; 31-54
2300-1976
Pojawia się w:
Rocznik Tomistyczny
Dostawca treści:
Biblioteka Nauki
Artykuł
Tytuł:
"Liber de definicionibus" i scholastyczny problem "adaequatio"
"Liber de definicionibus" and Scholastic Problem adaequatio
Autorzy:
Pawlikowski, Tomasz
Powiązania:
https://bibliotekanauki.pl/articles/452397.pdf
Data publikacji:
2015
Wydawca:
Naukowe Towarzystwo Tomistyczne
Tematy:
adaequatio
prawda
Izaak Izraeli
Albert Wielki
Tomasz z Akwinu
truth
Isaac Israeli
Albert the Great
Thomas Aquinas
Opis:
Thanks to historical and philosophical researches it is known for a long time that the definition “veritas est adequatio rei et intellectus” does not exist literally in any contemporary known lesson of Book of Definition. It is not eliminate the hypothesis that this definition of truth was in some manuscript which was known by scholastics in XIII century, e.g. as a gloss. It is not out of the question that it was wrongly diagnosis as a statement of Isaac Israeli. Analysis of quotes from this part in the Summa of Theology of Albert the Great about truth gives reasons to suppose that he used from manuscript which is similar in content to the manuscript which is in the Code of Munich 8001 but in contrast to text of Isaac Israeli it is not a shortened version. The basis of expression the definition “truth is a compatibility thing and intellect” probably was given by Isaac Israeli term: “the truth is corroborate thing about thing which [that thing] belongs truthfully or to reject thing from thing of which it is a truly rejected”. Supposedly on account of these things St. Thomas Aquinas refered on Isaac as an author of the definition of truth known today as “classic”, he kept in mind sense, not literal identity. Perhaps a gloss from unknowing manuscript suggested this sense or the established interpretation was the result of talks with the champion of Cologne. St. Albert evidently quoted the statement about the truth from Liber de definitionibus what we cannot say about Thomas. In a such situation an enigmatic character still has got an attribution of definition which is interesting for us. Aquinas could directly appeal to the works of Aristotle, in particular to the well-known a term of true appraise from Book IV of Metaphysics (1011b 27). The reason of connection the name of Isaac Israeli with adequatio idea could be that the Doctor Angelicus wanted introduce a definition which has got every kind of truth and at the same time he wanted to remain classical character understanding of it. Liber de definitionibus was good occasion because paraphrase of description true sentence in Aristotle’s think is really unclear. In addition Aristotle made revolutionary change ininterpretation the truth and he referred to an author whose views were not known very well.
Źródło:
Rocznik Tomistyczny; 2015, 4; 97-112
2300-1976
Pojawia się w:
Rocznik Tomistyczny
Dostawca treści:
Biblioteka Nauki
Artykuł
Tytuł:
Recenzja: Logika Marcina Śmigleckiego. Wprowadzenie, przegląd zagadnień, antologia tekstów, opracowali Roman Darowski SJ i Franciszek Bargieł SJ, Akademia Ignatianum w Krakowie, Wydawnictwo WAM, Kraków 2016, stron 316
Review: Logika Marcina Śmigleckiego. Wprowadzenie, przegląd zagadnień, antologia tekstów, opracowali Roman Darowski SJ i Franciszek Bargieł SJ, Akademia Ignatianum w Krakowie, Wydawnictwo WAM, Cracow 2016, pp. 316
Autorzy:
Pawlikowski, Tomasz
Powiązania:
https://bibliotekanauki.pl/articles/452656.pdf
Data publikacji:
2017
Wydawca:
Naukowe Towarzystwo Tomistyczne
Źródło:
Rocznik Tomistyczny; 2017, 6; 299-302
2300-1976
Pojawia się w:
Rocznik Tomistyczny
Dostawca treści:
Biblioteka Nauki
Artykuł
Tytuł:
Suárez i analogia w świetle nowych badań. Kazimierz Gryżenia SDB. Analogia w scholastyce nowożytnej. Studium z metafizyki Franciszka Suáreza. Lublin: Polskie Towarzystwo Tomasza z Akwinu, 2019, ss. 298. ISBN: 978-83-65792-18-1
Suárez and the Analogy in the Light of the New Research
Autorzy:
Pawlikowski, Tomasz
Powiązania:
https://bibliotekanauki.pl/articles/31232613.pdf
Data publikacji:
2021-12-06
Wydawca:
Katolicki Uniwersytet Lubelski Jana Pawła II. Towarzystwo Naukowe KUL
Źródło:
Roczniki Filozoficzne; 2021, 69, 4; 512-521
0035-7685
Pojawia się w:
Roczniki Filozoficzne
Dostawca treści:
Biblioteka Nauki
Artykuł
Tytuł:
Unikalny druk Ustaw Towarzystwa Strzelców Lwowskich z Księgozbioru Jakuba hr. Potockiego w zbiorach Biblioteki Publicznej m.st. Warszawy
A unique print of the laws of the Lwów Riflemen’s Association from the book collection of count Jakub Potocki, contemporary in the collection of the Public Library of the City of Warsaw
Autorzy:
Pawlikowski, Tomasz
Powiązania:
https://bibliotekanauki.pl/articles/27316741.pdf
Data publikacji:
2023-12-05
Wydawca:
Centralna Biblioteka Wojskowa im Marszałka Józefa Piłsudskiego
Tematy:
obronność
kultura fizyczna
Towarzystwo Strzelców Lwowskich
Wincenty Ziętkiewicz
zbiory biblioteczne
defense
physical culture
Society of Lviv Riflemen
library collections
Opis:
Celem artykułu jest zwrócenie uwagi na druk Regulativ des privilegirten burgerlichen Scharfschutzen-Corps der k.k. Hauptstadt Lemberg z 1817 roku, pochodzący z daru Jakuba hr. Potockiego dla Biblioteki Publicznej m.st. Warszawy, która obecnie pełni również funkcję Biblioteki Głównej Województwa Mazowieckiego. Autor dokonuje także analizy treści dzieła, przedstawia biogram twórcy i tło historyczne okresu, w którym ono powstało. Jest to być może jedyny zachowany egzemplarz i istotny dokument dotyczący działalności Towarzystwa Strzelców Lwowskich na początku XIX wieku. Kontynuowało ono tradycje wcześniejszego bractwa kurkowego, zwanego konfraternią, zasłużonego kilkukrotnie w obronie Lwowa. Również Towarzystwo Strzelców i jego działalność, łącząca aspekt militarny i sportowy, wpisały się w historię miasta.
The purpose of the article is to draw attention to the print, which comes from the gift of Count Jakub Potocki for the Warsaw Public Library (actually also Central Library of the Masovian Voivodship), Regulativ des privilegirten bürgerlichen Scharfschützen-Corps der k.k. Hauptstadt Lemberg from 1817, as well as an analysis of its content, recalling the author’s biography and the historical background in which it was created. It is perhaps the only surviving copy and a significant document concerning the activities of the Society of Lviv Riflemen at the beginning of the 19th century. It continued the traditions of the earlier Fowler Brotherhood, known as the Confraternity, which had served several times in defense of Lviv. However, the activity of the Society, combining the military and sports aspects, also entered the history of the city.
Źródło:
Studia i Materiały Centralnej Biblioteki Wojskowej; 2023, 1, 19; 105-129
2354-0435
2719-8618
Pojawia się w:
Studia i Materiały Centralnej Biblioteki Wojskowej
Dostawca treści:
Biblioteka Nauki
Artykuł
Tytuł:
Mistyk i działacz religijny w ujęciu ks. Aleksandra Usowicza
Mystic and religious activist in the view of Aleksander Usowicz CM
Autorzy:
Pawlikowski, Tomasz
Powiązania:
https://bibliotekanauki.pl/articles/452391.pdf
Data publikacji:
2017
Wydawca:
Naukowe Towarzystwo Tomistyczne
Tematy:
mistycyzm
aktywność
życie religijne
filozoficzna psychologia
tomizm
Aleksander Usowicz CM
mysticism
activity
religious life
philosophical psychology
thomism
Opis:
One of the most important issues raised in the work of Aleksander Usowicz CM (1912–2002) is a question of the relation¬ship between mysticism and action in re¬ligious life. The conclusions he has reached are interesting even today. They can be collected in the following 4 or 5 points. 1. Against to the opinion of many psy¬chologists, mysticism and religious ac¬tivity, which is typical for prophets, are not so much opposed between each oth¬er. One and the same man can experi¬ence typical mystical experiences and display prophetic activity at the same time. This is proved by historical exam¬ples. So, there are both mystics and prophets, but being a mystic and being a prophet – an activist does not have to be mutually exclusive in individual cases. 2. The characteristic feature of mys¬tics is experiencing ecstatic states, and in some cases, authentic stigmata. The ec¬static state is something that appears at the highest stage of proper mystical ex-periences, in the contemplation of the divine nature, when the soul rises above the sensual level. Both the contempla¬tion as well as the ecstasy accompanying or following it, they are purely mental and therefore spiritual. In itself, the ec¬stasy is a moment of happiness, but a way out of ecstatic states is painful, due to the loss of happiness and a specific “return to body”. The reason of this pain is that the body needs time to get out of the numbness and temporary disappearance of natural functions. States of this kind are authentic, just as stigmatization under the influence of divine action. However, in the latter case, Fr. A. Usowicz spoke more moderately. He admitted cases of signs that were not artificially wounded, which resemble stigmata, but may have a natural origin. 3. Contrary to some contemporary conceptions, searching for the patholog¬ical origin of mystical experiences is a mis¬take. Just as H. Bergson, Fr. A. Usow¬icz indicated that the famous mystics showed the ability to act and to cope in different circumstances, an accurate as¬sessment of their own abilities and com¬mon sense. He claimed, the appearance of elements deviating from the general standards results from the extraordinary intensity of the psychic energy of the mystics. He recognized them as justified in specific circumstances. He claimed that the integration of all mental activi¬ties into the mystic’s religious life was evidence of one’s mental health. 4. Similarly, the question of asceticism must be interpreted, because asceticism is a specific set of psychophysical exer¬cises for the development of religious spirituality. It is not true that authentic asceticism results in withdrawal from an activity or in a simplistic and inadequate image of reality. In response to this type of position, Cracovian Thomist formu¬lated criteria for healthy asceticism: (a) the assignment of the activity to the ob¬ject; (b) the synthesis of efforts on one primary goal; (c) the creative evolution resulting in enrichment and strengthen¬ing of the human spirit. 5. Complementing these proposals is the thesis that religious phenomena can not be explained without going beyond the psychological considerations. It is im¬possible to finally explain the existence of various manifestations of religions without referring them to God – the Transcendent Being. Recognition of the existence of God as initiating the reli¬gious life of man is a condition for dis-cerning the differences between natural and supernatural phenomena on the ba¬sis of empirically discernable features. The consequence of the rejection of this thesis is to reduce the genesis of all man¬ifestations of religious life to natural fac¬tors. This excludes a priori attempt to find the differences between the natural and the supernatural element. Although the thesis of the existence of God does not belong to psychology, it is important in the psychological interpretation of mysticism.
Źródło:
Rocznik Tomistyczny; 2017, 6; 167-188
2300-1976
Pojawia się w:
Rocznik Tomistyczny
Dostawca treści:
Biblioteka Nauki
Artykuł
Tytuł:
Problem subsystencji w "Logice" Marcina Śmigleckiego
The problem of Subsistence in "The Logic" of Marcin Śmiglecki
Autorzy:
Pawlikowski, Tomasz
Powiązania:
https://bibliotekanauki.pl/articles/452510.pdf
Data publikacji:
2016
Wydawca:
Naukowe Towarzystwo Tomistyczne
Tematy:
Marcin Śmiglecki
the second scholasticism
subsistence
substance
being
druga scholastyka
subsystencja
substancja
byt
Opis:
Marcin Śmiglecki (1564-1618) was one of the most famous Polish representatives of the second scholastics. His work Logica, originally published in Ingolstadt (1618), was followed by three times published at Oxford (1634, 1638 and 1658).This work includes a series of logical and metaphysical problems, issue of subsistence among them the. This issue belongs to the metaphysical problematics of the substance and is associated with the concept of being. An outline of the issues of subsistence, which we find in The Logic (1618), is very important, because in the earlier lectures in Vilnius (1586/1587), our thinker barely mentioned it. The problem was discussed in the Christian tradition. On the manner its consideration influenced mainly views of Boethius (c. 480-525), who understood the subsistence as a substance take on the aspect of independent existence. This idea developed St. Thomas Aquinas (1225- 1275) in accordance with its metaphysics of existence. The concept of subsistence meant for him independence in existence understood as the act of being. Generally, the second scholasticism, which was founded on the tradition of “pure” Aristotelianism, marginalized this question. We find this expressed in the views of Francisco Suárez (1548-1617), who claimed that “to subsist” means only one of many properties of the substance and that does not matter for the theory of being. However, for Śmiglecki, the concept of subsistence was essentially important. In the field of contingent beings it enabled him to positive statement the substance as being able to exist by itself. It was a generally valid definition of subsistence, especially referring to substances created. In this meaning “the subsistence” marked the independent existence, not inherent in the substrate. In the second and the crucial meaning, the subsistence is characterized by independence from any cause. This is the case of God’s Substance, Existence itself by itself. It seems that the great advantage of the concept of subsistence in Śmiglecki’s theory was that it allowed to accurately distinguish between substance created and the uncreated. The solution of this difficult problem was made possible by drawing attention to the existential aspect of being. Aquinas’ theory of being suggested this solution, but in the period of second scholasticism Aristotelian metaphysics was favorited. Thomistic accents were probable the cause that Śmiglecki’s Logic was initially negatively censured in Roma (1615). This is the fact, in his fundamental work our author walked away from some interpretations introduced by F. Suárez and masters of Jesuits school, but finally that gave great effects.
Źródło:
Rocznik Tomistyczny; 2016, 5; 305-328
2300-1976
Pojawia się w:
Rocznik Tomistyczny
Dostawca treści:
Biblioteka Nauki
Artykuł
Tytuł:
Metafizyka w marksizmie? – Materializm dialektyczny i jego konsekwencje w ujęciu o. Józefa Marii Bocheńskiego
Autorzy:
Pawlikowski, Tomasz
Powiązania:
https://bibliotekanauki.pl/articles/1966262.pdf
Data publikacji:
2020-12-30
Wydawca:
Naukowe Towarzystwo Tomistyczne
Tematy:
marksizm
metafizyka
sowietologia
Józef M. Bocheński
Marxism
Metaphysics
Sovietology
Joseph M. Bocheński
Opis:
Father Józef Maria Bocheński OP (1902– 1995) was considered a leading sovietologist. At the University of Fribourg, he founded in 1957 the Institute of Eastern Europe, in which the doctrine of Marxism-Leninism was studied scientifically. The results were published in the journal „Studies in Soviet Thought”. He initiated the uprising in Cologne Ost-Kolleg, where knowledge about Soviet philosophy and communism was disseminated. In the years 1961–1962 he was also its director. In his publications he undertook, among others the question of the metaphysics of Marxism, seeing it generally in dialectical materialism and, in specific applications, also in historical materialism. Criticizing this trend of thought, he focused on its latest findings, developed in the Soviet philosophy in the fifties of the twentieth century. Approaching the criticism from an external point of view, he pointed out some significant inconsistencies of Marxist materialism. According to the first law of dialectics, it proclaims a universal cause-effect determinism, and at the same time allows for the occurrence of random events. Explaining the existence of consciousness in matter with the adopted concept of cognition, Marxism mixes the epistemological and ontological order. Moreover, this trend uses the unscientific understanding of matter. On the basis of the considerations of Father Bocheński, it can also be concluded that the fundamental inconsistency of Marxist materialism is the acceptance of the existence of a spiritual element (consciousness) different in quality from mat-ter, while maintaining the thesis that there is only matter and what comes from it.
Źródło:
Rocznik Tomistyczny; 2020, 1, 9; 301-316
2300-1976
Pojawia się w:
Rocznik Tomistyczny
Dostawca treści:
Biblioteka Nauki
Artykuł
Tytuł:
Zagadnienie aktu stwórczego w kwestii 44 części I Sumy Teologicznej św. Tomasza z Akwinu
The Problem of the Act of Creation in Question 44, Part I of Thomas Aquinas’ Summa Theologica
Autorzy:
Pawlikowski, Tomasz
Powiązania:
https://bibliotekanauki.pl/articles/494676.pdf
Data publikacji:
2008
Wydawca:
Towarzystwo Naukowe Franciszka Salezego
Opis:
In Western theological and philosophical tradition, God is conceived to be the Creator of all that exists. The doctrine of creatio ex nihilo (creation out of nothing) has longstanding centrality in this understanding, by the time of Aquinas, concerns over the possibility of the universe itself existing from eternity led to thinking of creation out of nothing as the generic category of which initial creation. This doctrine involves, by St. Thomas Aquinas, areas of philosophical concern of Aristotle’s theory of four causes and Plato's theory of the participation, and the relationship between each. For Aquinas, the act of creation includes God’s activity as the efficient, exemplar and final cause every contigential things. The creation is the act whereby God brings a things into existence from a state of non-existence, but what is peculiar to creation is the entire absence of any prior subject-matter - ex nihilo subjecti. It is therefore likewise the production totius substantiæ - of the entire substance. The preposition ex, “out of”, imply that nihil, “nothing”, is to be conceived as the material out of which a thing is made - materia ex qua. Moreover, the things or beings as an object of the creative act in its entitative dependence on the Creator, it follows that, as this dependence is essential, and hence inamissible, the creative act once placed is coextensive in duration with the creature’s existence and perfections. This is the participative dependence beings created on God. What makes possible coherence between theory of four causes and theory of the beings participation is Aquinas’ theory of analogy. This is general theory in Aquinas’ metaphysics. The analogy of beings allows to show as coexistences two difference aspects of the same created things: its dependence on God as Prima Causa and on God as being absolutely perfect (the created beings aren’t perfect, but they participate in its own act of existence and own perfections created by God). God as being absolutely perfect – fullness of perfection is the Self-subsistens Being itself – Ipsum Esse per se subsistens.
Źródło:
Seminare. Poszukiwania naukowe; 2008, 25; 191-204
1232-8766
Pojawia się w:
Seminare. Poszukiwania naukowe
Dostawca treści:
Biblioteka Nauki
Artykuł
Tytuł:
The Problem of Democracy against the Background of the Theory of Origin and Authority in the Social Doctrine of the Church Fathers and St. Thomas Aquinas
Autorzy:
Pawlikowski, Tomasz
Powiązania:
https://bibliotekanauki.pl/articles/2098366.pdf
Data publikacji:
2020-12-31
Wydawca:
Uniwersytet Kardynała Stefana Wyszyńskiego w Warszawie
Tematy:
Theology
Democracy
Opis:
The modern social doctrine of the Catholic Church supports all of the abovementionedviews with the exception that it treats some of its elements as theso-called “signs of the times” in which the creators of these views lived andwrote. "erefore, we cannot say that they became somehow time-barred. "eyhave entered the tradition of the social doctrine of the Church. Similarly, onecannot reasonably claim that the basic theses of the socio-political theoriesof Saint Augustine or Saint "omas Aquinas are obsolete in philosophical terms.At the most, one can disagree with them or try to correct them. Nevertheless, itseems that there are no better analyses of the nature of authority and its originfrom God. Considering these issues from the perspective of historical applicationsof the theories, especially the one coined by St. "omas, it is impossible notto notice the significant analogies of the reflections of Doctor Angelicus and theidea of a “nobles’ democracy” implemented in the First Polish Republic threehundred years later. It is also difficult to believe that a$er the creation of thescientific community of the Jagiellonian University in the fi$eenth century, theydid not affect the minds of Polish politicians at a time when the foundationsof this democracy were formed. Moreover, it seems that these considerationswere widely applied in the centuries-old process of crystallizing other modernand contemporary democratic system.
Źródło:
Studia Theologica Varsaviensia; 2019; 661-670
0585-5594
Pojawia się w:
Studia Theologica Varsaviensia
Dostawca treści:
Biblioteka Nauki
Artykuł
    Wyświetlanie 1-14 z 14

    Ta witryna wykorzystuje pliki cookies do przechowywania informacji na Twoim komputerze. Pliki cookies stosujemy w celu świadczenia usług na najwyższym poziomie, w tym w sposób dostosowany do indywidualnych potrzeb. Korzystanie z witryny bez zmiany ustawień dotyczących cookies oznacza, że będą one zamieszczane w Twoim komputerze. W każdym momencie możesz dokonać zmiany ustawień dotyczących cookies